Good Reasons and Natural Ends: Rosalind Hursthouse’s Hermeneutical Naturalism
Rosalind Hursthouse (∗1943) is known chiefly both for her groundbreaking work in applying virtue ethics to practical matters and for her 1999 monograph On Virtue Ethics, which represents one of the first and few systematic treatments of modern virtue ethics and, in its central doctrines, remains highly influential to this day. The third and final part of this book is devoted to what is now known as neo-Aristotelian ethical naturalism, which in Hursthouse’s own words generally consists in “the enterprise of basing ethics in some way on considerations of human nature” (192). On her account, this project specifically aims at rendering the rationality of virtuous action intelligible by situating it in the wider context of human life.
This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.
Access this chapter
Subscribe and save
Springer+ Basic
€32.70 /Month
- Get 10 units per month
- Download Article/Chapter or eBook
- 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
- Cancel anytime
Buy Now
Price includes VAT (France)
eBook EUR 96.29 Price includes VAT (France)
Softcover Book EUR 126.59 Price includes VAT (France)
Hardcover Book EUR 147.69 Price includes VAT (France)
Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout
Purchases are for personal use only
Similar content being viewed by others
Foot Without Achilles’ Heel
Article 13 March 2019
From Good to God: Swami Vivekananda’s Vedāntic Virtue Ethics
Article 21 December 2022
A Humean particularist virtue ethic
Article 30 October 2014
Notes
Unless otherwise noted, all references are to Hursthouse (1999). Another comparably systematic development of modern virtue ethics, which appeared around the same time, is Müller (1998). For some of Hursthouse’s important contributions to applied ethics, cf. Hursthouse (1987, 1991, 1995, 2000, 2006, 2009, 2011).
Throughout this paper, I will use ‘practical thought’ and ‘ethical thought’ more or less interchangeably to refer to thought about what ought to be done.
This misunderstanding underlies a widespread line of criticism against neo-Aristotelian naturalism, which seeks to demonstrate that the traditional virtues are incompatible with, and therefore cannot be grounded in, a purely evolutionary or biological account of human beings. Cf. Andreou (2006), Millum (2006), and Millgram (2009). As will become apparent by the end of this paper, a similar misunderstanding also underlies Leist’s (2010, 136-141) charge that Hursthouse’s ‘biological’ naturalism fails due to its alleged reliance on an outdated vitalistic folk biology that has been refuted by post-Darwinian scientific biology.
Cf. Thompson (2004) and Hacker-Wright (2009) for comparable approaches.
Rehg and Davis (2003) argue that, since Hursthouse does not embrace a scientistic concept of nature, her virtue ethics cannot count as genuinely naturalistic either. Yet, if ‘naturalism’ merely means the attempt at providing an explanation, validation, or justification in terms of nature, then it leaves open which concept of nature to employ. It seems that, in principle, nothing precludes a normative concept of nature from doing this work. Rehg and Davis deny this by pointing out structural analogies between Hursthouse’s normative concept of human nature and a decidedly non-naturalistic Neo-Kantian concept of normativity. One may wonder, however, whether Rehg and Davis sufficiently heed the differences between these views and whether they do not, from the outset, formulate their criteria for a genuinely naturalistic concept of nature with scientism firmly in mind.
But note that critics such as Hare (1957), Pigden (1990), and Halbig (2015, 180–182) have questioned whether we do in fact employ ‘good’ consistently in a logically attributive manner. While I believe we do, on a proper understanding of logical attributiveness, I cannot argue the matter here for reasons of space.
Halbig (2015), 184–186, argues that the exclusion of health aspects from the overall evaluation of human beings represents a significant breach of continuity to other living beings, and that this seriously imperils the naturalistic character of ethical evaluation on Hursthouse’s account. It is important to note, however, that even among the other living beings there are significant differences regarding their aspects and natural ends. Clearly then, Hursthouse understands the continuity between the structures of evaluation that form part of different biological species concepts or natures not in terms of strict identity but rather in terms of family resemblance. Yet, speaking with McDowell, this allows for a ‘relaxed naturalism’ that is open to an essentially ethical form of evaluating living beings and a normative concept of human nature as essentially second nature.
Lott (2014) offers a systematic discussion of this objection as raised against neo-Aristotelian naturalism more generally.
A variant of the foundationalist picture also underlies Gowans’ (2008) charge that a “straightforward application of the Teleological Criterion” (52) allegedly formed by the four ends will not yield anything resembling our morality, and that in particular moral universalism cannot be derived from it. That is, Gowans treats the four ends as a criterion that we can apply to test ethical beliefs directly. Yet, this is not Hursthouse’s intent. Although the four ends are meant to guide ethical thought and argument somehow, they are not meant to effectively replace it with a quasi-technical decision procedure of this kind.
Cf. Müller (1992) for a discussion of this essentially ‘unreasoned’ teleology.
For ‘hinge propositions’, cf. Wittgenstein (1974), §§341–343, and Schönbaumsfeld (2016). In her attempt at uncovering the logical grammar of ethical thought, Hursthouse (208–211; 2004, 269–271) not only argues that the reasons of virtue in fact reflect these four ends, but also that other ethical theories contain traces of them. In line with Wittgenstein’s therapeutic conception of philosophy, these theories are thereby shown to be one-sided or otherwise defective explications of our actual practice, which ultimately threaten to corrupt it.
Cf. Hacker-Wright (2013) for a similar interpretation of the four ends. For a critical perspective, cf. Brüllmann (2013).
References
- Andreou, C. (2006). Getting on in a varied world. Social Theory and Practice, 32(1), 61–73. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Annas, J. (2005). Virtue ethics: What kind of naturalism? In S. Gardiner (Ed.), Virtue ethics, old and new (pp. 11–29). Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Google Scholar
- Brüllmann, P. (2013). Good (as) human beings. In J. Peters (Ed.), Aristotelian ethics in contemporary perspective (pp. 97–113). New York: Routledge. Google Scholar
- Copp, D., & Sobel, D. (2004). Morality and virtue. An assessment of some recent work in virtue ethics. Ethics, 114(3), 514–554. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Foot, P. (2001). Natural goodness. Oxford: Oxford University Press. BookGoogle Scholar
- Geach, P. (1956). Good and evil. Analysis, 17(2), 33–42. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Gowans, C. (2008). Virtue and nature. Social Philosophy and Policy, 25(1), 28–55. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Hacker-Wright, J. (2009). What is natural about Foot’s ethical naturalism? Ratio, 22(3), 308–321. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Hacker-Wright, J. (2013). Human nature, virtue, and rationality. In J. Peters (Ed.), Aristotelian ethics in contemporary perspective (pp. 83–96). New York: Routledge. Google Scholar
- Halbig, C. (2015). Ein Neustart der Ethik? Zur Kritik des aristotelischen Naturalismus. In M. Rothhaar & M. Hähnel (Eds.), Normativität des Lebens – Normativität der Vernunft? (pp. 175–197). Berlin: De Gruyter. ChapterGoogle Scholar
- Hare, R. (1957). Geach: Good and evil. Analysis, 17(5), 103–111. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Hursthouse, R. (1987). Beginning lives. Oxford: Blackwell. Google Scholar
- Hursthouse, R. (1991). Virtue theory and abortion. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 20(3), 223–246. Google Scholar
- Hursthouse, R. (1995). Applying virtue ethics. In R. Hursthouse, G. Lawrence, & W. Quinn (Eds.), Virtues and reasons. Philippa Foot and moral theory (pp. 57–75). Oxford: Clarendon. Google Scholar
- Hursthouse, R. (1999). On virtue ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Google Scholar
- Hursthouse, R. (2000). Ethics, humans and other animals. London: Routledge. Google Scholar
- Hursthouse, R. (2002). Virtue ethics vs. rule-consequentialism: A reply to Brad hooker. Utilitas, 14(1), 41–53. Google Scholar
- Hursthouse, R. (2004). On the grounding of the virtues in human nature. In J. Szaif & M. Lutz-Bachmann (Eds.), Was ist das für den Menschen Gute? Menschliche Natur und Güterlehre/What is Good for a Human Being? Human Nature and Values (pp. 263–275). Berlin: De Gruyter. ChapterGoogle Scholar
- Hursthouse, R. (2006). Applying virtue ethics to our treatment of the other animals. In J. Welchman (Ed.), The practice of virtue. Classic and contemporary readings in virtue ethics (pp. 136–155). Indianapolis: Hackett. Google Scholar
- Hursthouse, R. (2009). Environmental virtue ethics. In R. Walker & P. Ivanhoe (Eds.), Working virtue: Virtue ethics and contemporary moral problems (pp. 155–172). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Google Scholar
- Hursthouse, R. (2011). Virtue ethics and the treatment of animals. In T. Beauchamp & R. G. Frey (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of animal ethics (pp. 119–143). Oxford: Oxford University Press. ChapterGoogle Scholar
- Hursthouse, R. (2012). Human nature and Aristotelian virtue ethics. In C. Sandis & M. J. Cain (Eds.), Human nature (Royal Institute of Philosophy supplement) (Vol. 70, pp. 169–188). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Google Scholar
- Leist, A. (2010). Wie moralisch ist unsere menschliche Natur? Naturalismus bei Foot und Hursthouse. In T. Hoffmann & M. Reuter (Eds.), Natürlich gut. Aufsätze zur Philosophie von Philippa Foot (pp. 121–148). Frankfurt am Main: Ontos. ChapterGoogle Scholar
- Lemos, J. (2007). Foot and Aristotle on virtues and flourishing. Philosophia, 35(1), 43–62. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Lott, M. (2014). Why be a good human being? Natural goodness, reason, and the authority of human nature. Philosophia, 42(3), 761–777. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- McDowell, J. (1995). Two sorts of naturalism. In R. Hursthouse, G. Lawrence, & W. Quinn (Eds.), Virtues and reasons. Philippa Foot and moral theory (pp. 149–179). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Google Scholar
- Millgram, E. (2009). Life and action. Analysis, 69(3), 557–564. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Millum, J. (2006). Natural goodness and natural evil. Ratio, 19(2), 199–213. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Müller, A. W. (1992). Mental teleology. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 92, 161–184. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Müller, A. W. (1998). Was taugt die Tugend? Elemente einer Ethik des guten Lebens. Stuttgart: Kohlhammer. Google Scholar
- Pigden, C. (1990). Geach on good. The Philosophical Quarterly, 40(159), 129–154. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Rehg, W., & Davis, D. (2003). Conceptual gerrymandering? The alignment of hursthouse’s naturalistic virtue ethics with neo-kantian non-naturalism. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 41(4), 583–600. Google Scholar
- Schönbaumsfeld, G. (2016). ‘Hinge propositions’ and the ‘logical’ exclusion of doubt. International Journal for the Study of Skepticism, 6(2–3), 165–181. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Thompson, M. (2004). Apprehending human form. In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Modern moral philosophy (Royal Institute of Philosophy supplement) (Vol. 54, pp. 47–74). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ChapterGoogle Scholar
- Williams, B. (1995). Evolution, ethics, and the representation problem. In Making sense of humanity (pp. 100–110). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ChapterGoogle Scholar
- Wittgenstein, L. (1974). Über Gewissheit. On Certainty [1969]. (Ed. by G. E. M. Anscombe, G. H. von Wright. Corr. Ed.). Oxford: Blackwell. Google Scholar
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
- University of Trier, Trier, Germany Sascha Settegast
- Sascha Settegast